"Meaning is Use" and Wittgenstein’s Treatment of Philosophical Problems
Keywords:
Wittgenstein Ludwig, 20th century philosophy, meaning, use, method, therapeutic readingAbstract
What is the relation between later Wittgenstein’s method of dissolving philosophical problems by reminding us of how we would actually use words, and his famous statement that “meaning is use” in Investigations §43? The idea is widespread among readers of Wittgenstein that a close relation obtains between the two. This paper addresses a specific type of answer to this question: answers which have drawn on remarks of Wittgenstein’s where he explicitly establishes a connection between this method and certain misconceptions about meaning – remarks such as Investigations §117. The paper will discuss answers which have advanced the following claim: Since it is places such as §43 which play a main role in debunking misconceptions of this kind, Wittgenstein’s statement that “meaning is use” must be taken as directly related to the method of asking for the use of words. Drawing on so-called “therapeutic” readings of Wittgenstein, what I intend to show is that this seemingly straightforward answer fails to fully accommodate the fact that §43 is itself a reminder of how we would actually use a word. The paper sets out to show how truly acknowledging this forces us to rethink the relation between “meaning is use” and this method of Wittgenstein’s.References
Conant, J., 1998. “Wittgenstein on Meaning and Use”. Philosophical Investigations, 21 (3), pp. 222-250.
Conant, J., 1999. “Comment on Diamond’s ‘Unfolding Truth and Reading Wittgenstein’”. Presentation to the APA (manuscript).
Conant, J., 2004. “Why Worry about the Tractatus?”. In: B. Stocker, ed. 2004. Post-Analytic Tractatus. Aldershot: Ashgate, pp. 167-192.
Crary, A. / Read, R., ed. 2000. The New Wittgenstein. London / New York: Routledge.
Diamond, C., 2004. “Criss-Cross Philosophy”. In: E. Ammereller / E. Fischer, ed. 2004. Wittgenstein at Work. Method in the Philosophical Investigations. London / New York: Routledge, pp. 201-220.
Giesewetter, S., 2011. Resolute Readings of Later Wittgenstein and the Challenge of Avoiding Hierarchies in Philosophy (dissertation). Potsdam: Institutional Repository of the Universität Potsdam (online publication).
Gustafsson, M., 2006. “Nonsense and Philosophical Method”. In:
S. Pihlström, ed. 2006. Wittgenstein and the Method of Philosophy. Acta Philosophica Fennica 80, pp. 11-34.
Hacker, P. M. S., 1991. “Experimental Methods and Conceptual Confusion: An Investigation into R. L. Gregory’s Theory of Perception”. Iyyun 40, pp. 289-314.
Hacker, P. M. S., 2005a. Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning – An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations, Volume 1, Part I: Essays. Second, extensively revised edition. Oxford: Blackwell.
Hacker, P. M. S., 2005b. Wittgenstein: Understanding and Meaning – An Analytical Commentary on the Philosophical Investigations, Volume 1, Part II: Exegesis §§1–184. Second, extensively revised edition. Oxford: Blackwell
Horwich, P., 2012. Wittgenstein’s Metaphilosophy. Oxford: Oxford University Press.
Kuusela, O., 2008. The Struggle against Dogmatism. Wittgenstein and the Concept of Philosophy. Cambridge, Mass.: Harvard University Press.
Wittgenstein, L., 1953. Philosophical Investigations. Trans. G. E. M. Anscombe. Oxford: Blackwell.
Wittgenstein, L., 1976, Wittgenstein’s Lectures on the Foundations of Mathematics: Cambridge, 1939, ed. Cora Diamond. Ithaca: Cornell University Press.
Wittgenstein, L., 1979. Wittgenstein’s Lectures, Cambridge, 1932-35, ed. Alice Ambrose. Oxford: Blackwell.
Downloads
Published
Issue
Section
License
NWR uses the Creative Commons license CC-BY.
Vol. 1-3 used CC-BY-NC-SA. The collected works copyright ownership for Vol. 1-2 were shared by Nordic Wittgenstein Society and ontos Verlag/De Gruyter.